Source: http://www.nizkor.org Accessed 18 October 1999 IN THE DISTRICT COURT OF JERUSALEM Criminal Case No. 40/61 Before His Honour JUDGE MOSHE LANDAU (Presiding) His Honour JUDGE BENJAMIN HALEVI His Honour JUDGE YITZCHAK RAVEH For the Prosecution: THE ATTORNEY GENERAL The Accused: ADOLF, son
of Karl Adolf, EICHMANN Judgment in the Trial of Adolf Eichmann [Part 1] The references in the Judgment
are to the official record in Hebrew. Adolf Eichmann has been brought
to trial in this Court on charges of unsurpassed gravity - charges of
crimes against the Jewish People, crimes
against humanity, and war crimes. The
period of the crimes ascribed
to him, and their historical background, is that of the Hitler regime in
Germany and in Europe, and the counts of the indictment encompass the
catastrophe which befell the Jewish People during that period - a story
of bloodshed and suffering which will be remembered to the end of time. This is not the first time that
the Holocaust has been discussed in court proceedings. It was dealt with extensively at the International Military
Tribunal at Nuremberg during the Trial of the Major War Criminals, and
also at several of the trials which followed; but this time it has
occupied the central place in the Court proceedings, and it is this fact
which has distinguished this trial from those which preceded it.
Hence also the trend noticed during and around the trial, to
widen its range. The desire
was felt - understandable in itself - to give, within the trial, a
comprehensive and exhaustive historical description of events which
occurred during the Holocaust, and in so doing, to emphasize also the
inconceivable feats of heroism performed by ghetto-fighters, by those
who mutinied in the camps, and by Jewish partisans. There are also those who sought
to regard this trial as a forum for the clarification of questions of
great import, some of which arose from the Holocaust, while others, of
long standing but which have now emerged once again in more acute form,
because of the unprecedented sufferings which were visited upon the
Jewish People and the world as a whole in the middle of the Twentieth
Century. How could this happen in the
light of day, and why was it just the German people from which this
great evil sprang? Could
the Nazis have carried out their evil designs without the help given
them by other peoples in whose midst the Jews dwelt?
Would it have been possible to avert the Holocaust, at least in
part, if the Allies had displayed a greater will to assist the
persecuted Jews? Did the
Jewish People in the lands of freedom do all in its power to rally to
the rescue of its brethren and to sound the alarm for help?
What are the psychological and social causes of the group-hatred
which is known as anti-Semitism? Can this ancient disease be cured, and by what means?
What is the lesson which the Jews and other nations must draw
from all this, as well as every person in his relationship to others?
There are many other questions of various kinds which cannot even
all be listed. 2. In this maze of insistent
questions, the path of the Court was and remains clear.
It cannot allow itself to be enticed into provinces which are
outside its sphere. The
judicial process has ways of its own, laid down by law, and which do not
change, whatever the subject of the trial may be.
Otherwise, the processes of law and of court procedure are bound
to be impaired, whereas they must be adhered to punctiliously, since
they are in themselves of considerable social and educational
significance, and the trial would otherwise resemble a rudderless ship
tossed about by the waves. It is the purpose of every
criminal trial to clarify whether the charges in the prosecution's
indictment against the accused who is on trial are true, and if the
accused is convicted, to mete out due punishment to him.
Everything which requires clarification in order that these
purposes may be achieved, must be determined at the trial, and
everything which is foreign to these purposes must be entirely
eliminated from the court procedure. Not only is any pretension to overstep these limits forbidden
to the court - it would certainly end in complete failure.
The court does not have at its disposal the tools required for
the investigation of general questions of the kind referred to above.
For example, in connection with the description of the historical
background of the Holocaust, a great amount of material was brought
before us in the form of documents and evidence, collected most
painstakingly, and certainly in a genuine attempt to delineate as
complete a picture as possible. Even
so, all this material is but a tiny fraction of all that is extant on
this subject. According to
our legal system, the court is by its very nature "passive,"
for it does not itself initiate the bringing of proof before it, as is
the custom with an enquiry commission.
Accordingly, its ability to describe general events is inevitably
limited. As for questions
of principle which are outside the realm of law, no one has made us
judges of them, and therefore no greater weight is to be attached to our
opinion on them than to that of any person devoting study and thought to
these questions. These prefatory remarks do not
mean that we are unaware of the great educational value, implicit in the
very holding of this trial, for those who live in Israel as well as for
those beyond the confines of this state.
To the extent that this result has been achieved in the course of
the proceedings, it is to be welcomed.
Without a doubt, the testimony given at this trial by survivors
of the Holocaust, who poured out their hearts as they stood in the
witness box, will provide valuable material for research workers and
historians, but as far as this Court is concerned, they are to be
regarded as by-products of the trial. 3. Before we deal with the case
itself, we desire to express our appreciation to the representatives of
both parties, who laboured in the presentation of this case.
The Attorney General, Mr. Hausner, and his assistants, Dr.
Robinson, Mr. Bar-Or, Mr. Bach, and Mr. Terlo, who helped in the conduct
of the case, carried an enormous burden on their shoulders, and
displayed absolute mastery of the huge amount of legal and factual
material prepared for them by the police investigators, who toiled
before them in a manner which also deserves praise.
The Attorney General himself emerged honourably from the dilemma,
to which we alluded above, and which he, too, certainly felt in all its
full impact. In spite of a
slight deviation here and there from the narrow path which the Court saw
as its duty to set, Mr. Hausner conducted the prosecution in its stages
as a jurist and on a very high professional level.
In his brilliant opening speech, which was eloquent and broad in
perspective, and again in his concluding statement, he gave vent also to
the deep feelings which stir the entire nation.
Similarly, we wish to express our appreciation to Counsel for the
Defence, Dr. Servatius, and his assistant, Mr. D. Wechtenbruch.
Dr. Servatius, who stood almost alone in this strenuous legal
battle, in an unfamiliar environment, always directed himself to the
essence of the matter, and refrained from unnecessary controversy over
matters which did not seem vital to him for the defence of his client,
thereby affording valuable assistance to the Court.
Thus even some uncalled-for notes in his concluding speech, which
jarred on our ears, could not detract from the worthy and serious
impression made by his arguments for the Defence as a whole. 4. At the
outset, we must state
the reasons for our Decision (No. 3 given on 17 April 1961, Session 6)
relating to our jurisdiction to try this case.
It is the duty of the Court to examine its competence ex officio
even without the question having been raised by the Accused; indeed,
even if the Accused had consented to be tried by this Court, we would
not have been entitled to try him unless the law empowers us so to do.
The law which confers on us jurisdiction to try the Accused in
this case is the Nazis and Nazi Collaborators (Punishment) Law 5710-1950
(hereinafter referred to, for short, as "the Israeli Law,"
"the Law in question" or "the Law"). Section 1(a) of the Law
provides: "A
person who has committed one of the following offences (1) during the period of the Nazi regime in a hostile
country, carried out an act constituting a crime against the Jewish
People; (2)
during the period of the Nazi regime, carried out an act constituting a
crime against humanity, in a hostile country; (3)
during the period of the Second World War, carried out an act
constituting a war crime, in a hostile country; is liable to the death
penalty." The three above-mentioned
classes of crimes - crime against the Jewish People, crime against
humanity, war crime - are defined in Section 1(b) (see infra) - Section 3(a) provides: "A
person who, during the period of the Nazi regime, was a member of, or
held any post or exercised any function, in a hostile organization, in a
hostile country, is liable to imprisonment for a term not exceeding
seven years." "A hostile
organization" is defined in Section 3(b) (see infra).
Section 16 defines the terms "the period of the Nazi
regime," "the period of the Second World War," and
"a hostile country." 5. In Criminal Appeal 22/52,
Honigman v. Attorney General (7 Piske Din 296, 303), Justice Cheshin
stated: "The
Law in question is designed to make it possible to try in Israel Nazis,
their associates and their collaborators for the murder of the Jewish
People...and for crimes against humanity as a whole...this particular
legislation is totally different from any other usual legislation in
criminal codes: The Law is retroactive and extra-territorial..." Indeed, the expressions "in
a hostile country," "during the period of the Nazi
regime" and "during the period of the Second World War,"
which define the application of the Law in point of place and in point
of time, indicate unequivocally that the crimes are "foreign
crimes" and that the Law has retroactive application.
These two elements do indeed diverge from the characteristics of
usual criminal legislation which generally looks to the future and not -
or at least not only - to the past; to the home country and not - or at
least not only - abroad; but these elements necessarily derive from the
very object of the Law for the Punishment of Nazis and their
Collaborators. 6. Under Sections 6 and 7 of the
Criminal Code Ordinance, 1936, the ordinary jurisdiction of the courts
of Israel extends to any act committed in whole or in part within the
boundaries of the state or within the three nautical miles territorial
coastal limit, but Section 3(b) adds that nothing in the Ordinance shall
derogate from the "liability of any persons to be tried and
punished for any offence according to the provisions of the law on the
jurisdiction of the Israeli courts with respect to acts committed
outside the ordinary jurisdiction of these courts."
One of the laws which establishes the jurisdiction of Israeli
courts with respect to certain classes of offences committed abroad is
the Criminal Law Amendment (Foreign Offences) Law, 5716-1955.
Another law of this order is the Law in question here. 7. The question as to whether
the Israeli legislator may enact a criminal law with retroactive effect
was considered in the first criminal case heard in this District Court
after the establishment of the State and in the first appeal lodged with
the Supreme Court of Israel, Criminal Appeal 1/48, Sylvester v. Attorney
General (Pesakim I, 513, 528). Justice
Smoira, the first President of the Supreme Court, said in his judgment,
inter alia: "As
regards the distinction between retroactive laws and ex post facto
laws... I now revert to the judgment of Justice Willes in Phillips v.
Eyre (L.Q. (1871) 6 Q.B. 1, at p. 25).
He stated: "Justice
Blackstone (Comm. 46) describes laws ex post facto of this objectionable
class as those by which `after an action indifferent in itself is
committed, the legislator then for the first time declares it to have
been a crime, and inflicts a punishment upon the person who has
committed it. Here it is
impossible that the party could foresee that an action, innocent when it
was done, should be afterwards converted to guilt by a subsequent law;
he had, therefore, no cause to abstain from it and all punishment for
not abstaining must of consequence be cruel and unjust...'
In fine, allowing the general inexpediency of retrospective
legislation, it cannot be pronounced naturally or necessarily unjust.
There may be occasions and circumstances involving the safety of
the state, or even the conduct of individual subjects, the justice of
which prospective laws, made for ordinary occasions and the usual
exigencies of society, for want of prevision fail to meet, and in which
the execution of the law as it stood at the time may involve practical
public inconvenience and wrong, summum jus summa injuria.
Whether the circumstances of the particular case are such as to
call for special and exceptional remedy is a question which must in each
case involve matter of policy and discretion fit for debate and decision
in the parliament which would have had jurisdiction to deal with the
subject matter by preliminary legislation, and as to which a court of
ordinary municipal law is not commissioned to inquire or
adjudicate." "...
I am unable to add with gratification," continued the President,
"that in acknowledging the retroactive effect of the law in
question I am far from acknowledging a `barbaric' law, for it is
precisely in pursuance with Justice Blackstone's definition that I hold
that it cannot be said that the act of which the appellant was accused
was `an action indifferent in itself, and only subsequently the
legislator declared it for the first time to have been a crime.'
The legislation with retrospective effect, here dealt with, has
not created a new crime which had not hitherto been known in the
Occupied Area of Jerusalem, and it cannot therefore be said that the
person who commits the act of which the appellant is accused did not
have a criminal intent (mens rea), because he did not and could not know
that the act he was doing was a criminal act.
On the contrary, it stands to reason that he who has actually
committed such an act knew that an act of this kind is a crime.
I, therefore, hold that by concluding that the Official Secrets
Ordinance has retroactive effect, I do not come in conflict with the
rules of natural justice or elementary equity." The President gave his judgment
before the enactment of the Nazis and Nazi Collaborators (Punishment)
Law, but his remarks are apt and relevant to our case.
There is no subject of which it can be said with greater justice
that "the usual laws enacted in ordinary circumstances and for the
usual needs of society fall short of meeting the dictates of justice and
law" (ibid., p. 532) than the subject of the Nazi crimes against
humanity in general, and the Jewish People in particular.
Not one of the crimes defined in the Law in question was, in the
words of Blackstone, "an indifferent action when committed, and
subsequently declared for the first time by the legislator to have been
a crime." Neither has
the retroactive legislation herein dealt with "created a new crime
which had not hitherto been known" in Germany or German-occupied
territories. On the
contrary, all the aboveŞmentioned crimes constituted crimes under the
laws of all civilized nations, including the German people, before and
after the Nazi regime, while the "law" and criminal decrees of
Hitler and his regime are not laws, and have been set aside with
retroactive effect even by the German courts themselves (see infra). It cannot be said that the
perpetrators of the crimes defined in the Law in question "could
not have a mens rea because they did not and could not know that what
they were doing was a criminal act" (ibid).
The extensive measures taken by the Nazis to efface the traces of
their crimes, such as the disinterment of the dead bodies of the
murdered and their cremation into ashes, or the destruction of the
Gestapo archives before the collapse of the Reich, clearly prove that
the Nazis knew well the criminal character of their enormities.
A law that authorizes the punishment of Nazis and their
collaborators does not "conflict," through its retroactive
application, "with the rules of natural justice," in the words
of the President; on the contrary, it enforces the dictates of
elementary justice. 8. Learned Counsel does not
ignore the fact that the Israeli Law applicable to the acts attributed
to the Accused vests in us the jurisdiction to try this case.
His contention against the jurisdiction of the Court is not based
on this Law, but on international law.
He contends - (a)that
the Israeli Law, by inflicting punishment for acts committed outside the
boundaries of the state and before its establishment, against persons
who were not Israeli citizens, and by a person who acted in the course
of duty on behalf of a foreign country ("Act of State")
conflicts with international law and exceeds the powers of the Israeli
legislator; (b)
that the prosecution of the Accused in Israel upon his abduction from a
foreign country conflicts with international law and exceeds the
jurisdiction of the Court. 9. Before entering upon an
analysis of these two contentions and the legal questions involved, we
will clarify the relation between them. These two contentions are
independent of each other. The
first contention, which negates the jurisdiction of the Court to try the
Accused for offences against the Law in question, is not bound up with,
or conditional upon, the circumstances under which he was brought to
Israel. Even had the Accused come to this country of his own free
will, say as a tourist under an assumed name, and had he been arrested
here upon the verification of his true identity, the first contention of
Counsel that the Israeli Court has no jurisdiction to try him for any
offences against the Law in question would still stand.
The second, additional, contention is that no matter what the
jurisdiction of the Israeli Court is to try offences attributed to the
Accused in ordinary circumstances, that jurisdiction is in any case
negated by reason of the special circumstances connected with the
abduction of the Accused in a foreign country and his prosecution in
Israel. We will therefore
deal with these two questions seriatim. 10. The first contention of
Counsel that Israel Law is in conflict with international law, and that
therefore it cannot vest jurisdiction in this Court, raises the
preliminary question as to the validity of international law in Israel
and as to whether, in the event of a conflict between it and the laws of
the land, it is to be preferred to the laws of the land.
The law in force in Israel resembles that which is in force in
England in this regard. See
Oppenheim (Lauterpacht), International Law, 8th Ed., 1955, para. 21a, p.
39: "As
regards Great Britain, the following points must be noted: (a) All such
rules of customary international law as are either universally
recognized or have, at any rate, received the assent of this country are
per se part of the law of the land.
To that extent there is still valid in England the common law
doctrine, to which Blackstone gave expression in a striking passage,
that the Law of Nations is part of the law of the land." But on the other hand (p. 41): "(c)
English statutory law is absolutely binding upon English courts, even if
in conflict with international law, although in doubtful cases there is
a presumption that an Act of Parliament did not intend to overrule
international law. The fact
that international law is part of the law of the land and is binding
directly on courts and individuals does not mean that English law
recognizes in all circumstances the supremacy of international law. (Note 3) It is of importance not
to confuse, as many do, the question of the supremacy of international
law and of the direct operation of its rules within the municipal
sphere. It is possible to
deny the former while fully affirming the latter." See also - Croft v. Dunphy
(1933) A.C. 156 (p. 164): "Legislation
of the Imperial Parliament, even in contravention of generally
acknowledged principles of international law, is binding upon and must
be enforced by the courts of this country, for in these courts the
legislation of the Imperial Parliament cannot be challenged as ultra
vires (Mortensen v. Peters)." And also - Polites v.
Commonwealth of Australia (1945) 70 C.L.R. 60 (Annual Digest, 1943-1945,
Case No. 61): "The
Commonwealth Parliament can legislate on these matters in breach of
international law, taking the risk of international complications.
This is recognized as being the position in Great Britain... The
position is the same in the United States of America... It must be held
that legislation otherwise within the power of the Commonwealth
Parliament does not become invalid because it conflicts with a rule of
international law, though every effort should be made to construe
Commonwealth statutes so as to avoid breaches of international law and
of international comity." As regards Israel, the Deputy
President, Justice Cheshin, said in Criminal Appeal 174/54 (10 Piske
Din, 5,p.17): "As
regards the question of the adoption by the national law of the
principles of international law, we may safely rely on Blackstone's view
in his Commentaries on the Laws of England (Book IV, Chap. 5): "`In
England...the law of nations...is...adopted in its full extent by the
common law, and is held to be part of the law of the land...without
which it must cease to be a part of the civilized world.' And that is the case in other
countries, such as the U.S.A., France, Belgium, and Switzerland, where
the usages of international law have been acknowledged as part of the
law of the land..." With respect to statutory law,
Justice Agranat said in High Court Case 279/51 (6 Piske Din 945, p.
966): "It
is a well known rule that a local statutory law must be construed in
accordance with the rules of public international law, unless its tenor
requires another interpretation." And in Criminal Appeal 5/51 (5
iske Din 1061), Justice Sussman said (p. 1065): "It
is a well-known rule that in interpreting the law, the court shall
endeavour, as far as possible, to avoid a clash between the national law
and the rules of international law which are binding upon the state; but
this rule is only one of the rules of interpretation.
When we are not dealing with the common law, but with statutory
law, where the will of the legislator is clear from its wording, the
will of the legislator must be enforced without regard to any
contradiction between that statutory law and international law...
Moreover, the courts of this country derive their jurisdiction not from
the system of international law but from the laws of the land." Our jurisdiction to try this
case is based on the Nazis and Nazi Collaborators (Punishment) Law, a
statutory law the provisions of which are unequivocal.
The Court has to give effect to the law of the Knesset, and we
cannot entertain the contention that this law conflicts with the
principles of international law. For
this reason alone, Counsel's first contention must be rejected. 11. But we have also perused the
sources of international law, including the numerous authorities
mentioned by learned Counsel in his comprehensive written brief upon
which he based his oral pleadings, and by the learned Attorney General
in his comprehensive oral pleadings, and have failed to find any
foundation for the contention that Israeli law is in conflict with the
principles of international law. On
the contrary, we have reached the conclusion that the Law in question
conforms to the best traditions of the law of nations. The power of the State of Israel
to enact the Law in question or Israel's "right to punish" is
based, with respect to the offences in question, from the point of view
of international law, on a dual foundation: The universal character of
the crimes in question and their specific character as being designed to
exterminate the Jewish People. In
what follows, we shall deal with each of these two aspects separately. 12. The abhorrent crimes defined
in this Law are crimes not under Israeli law alone.
These crimes which offended the whole of mankind and shocked the
conscience of nations are grave offences against the law of nations
itself ("delicta juris gentium").
Therefore, so far from international law negating or limiting the
jurisdiction of countries with respect to such crimes, in the absence of
an International Court, the international law is in need of the judicial
and legislative authorities of every country, to give effect to its
penal injunctions and to bring criminals to trial.
The jurisdiction to try crimes under international law is
universal. 13. This universal authority,
namely the authority of the "forum deprehensionis" (the court
of the country in which the accused is actually held in custody) was
already mentioned in the Corpus Juris Civilis (see: C. 3, 15, "ubi
de criminibus agi oportet"), and the towns of northern Italy had
already in the Middle Ages taken to trying specific types of dangerous
criminals ("banniti, vagabundi, assassini") who happened to be
within their area of jurisdiction, without regard to the place in which
the crimes in question were committed (see Donnedieu de Vabres Les
Principes Modernes du Droit Penal International, 1928, p. 136).
Maritime nations have also since time immemorial enforced the
principle of universal jurisdiction in dealing with pirates, whose crime
is known in English law as "piracy jure gentium."
See Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of England, Book IV,
Chap. 5 "Of Offences against the Law of Nations," p. 68: "The
principal offences against the law of nations, animadverted on as such
by the municipal laws of England, are of three kinds... 3. Piracy." p. 71: "Lastly,
the crime of piracy, or robbery and depredation upon the high seas, is
an offence against the universal law of society; a pirate being,
according to Sir Edward Coke (3 Inst. 113) hostis humani generis. As, therefore, he has renounced all the benefits of society
and government, and has reduced himself afresh to the savage state of
nature, by declaring war against all mankind, all mankind must declare
war against him; so that every community hath a right by the rule of
self-defence, to inflict that punishment upon him which every individual
would in a state of nature have been otherwise entitled to do, for any
invasion of his person or personal property." See also In re Piracy Jure
Gentium, (1934) A.C. 586 (per Viscount Sankey L.C.): "With
regard to crimes as defined by international law, that law has no means
of trying or punishing them. The
recognition of them as constituting crimes, and the trial and punishment
of the criminals, are left to the municipal law of each country.
But whereas according to international law the criminal
jurisdiction of municipal law is ordinarily restricted to crimes by its
own nationals wherever committed, it is also recognized as extending to
piracy committed on the high seas by any national on any ship, because a
person guilty of such piracy has placed himself beyond the protection of
any state. He is no longer
a national, but hostis humani generis, and as such he is justiciable by
any state anywhere." 14. Hugo Grotius had already in
1625 raised in his famous book De Jure Belli ac Pacis (On the Law of War
and Peace) the basic question of the "right to punish" under
international law, the very question learned Counsel raised. In Book Two, chapter 20 "De
Poenis" (On Punishment), the author says, inter alia: "Qui
punit, ut recte puniat, jus habere debet ad puniendum, quod jus ex
delicto nocentis nascitur." (In order that he who punishes may duly
punish, he must possess the right to punish, a right deriving from the
criminal's crime.) In the writer's view, the object
of punishment may be the good of the criminal, the good of the victim,
or the good of the community. According to natural justice, the victim
may take the law into his hand and himself punish the criminal, and it
is also permissible for any person of integrity to inflict punishment
upon the criminal; but all such natural rights have been limited by
organized society and have been delegated to the courts of law.
The learned author here adds these important words (our
emphasis): "Sciendum
quoque est reges, et qui par regibus jus obtinent, jus habere poenas
poscendi non tantum ob injurias in se aut subditos suos commissas, sed
et ob eas quae ipsos peculiariter non tangunt, sed in quibusvis personis
jus naturae aut gentium immaniter violantibus." (It must also be
known that kings, and any who have rights equal to the rights of kings,
may demand that punishment be imposed not only for wrongs committed
against them or their subjects, but also for all such wrongs as do not
specifically concern them, but violate in extreme formin relation to any
persons, the law of nature or the law of nations." And he goes on to explain: "Nam
libertas humanae societati per poenas consulendi, quae initio ut diximus
penes singulos fuerat, civitatibus ac judiciis institutis penes summas
potestates resedit, non proprie quo aliis imperant, sed qua nemini
parent. Nam subjectio aliis
id jus abstulit." (For the liberty to serve the welfare of human
society by imposing penalties which had at first been, as already
stated, in the hands of the individuals, has been exercised since the
constitution of states and courts, by those with the supreme authority,
not because they dominate others, but because they are subject to no
one. For subjection to
government has taken this right away from others.) It is therefore the moral duty
of every sovereign state (of "kings and any who have rights equal
to the rights of kings") to enforce the natural right to punish,
possessed by the victims of the crime whoever they may be, against
criminals whose acts have "violated in extreme form the law of
nature or the law of nations."
By these pronouncements the father of international law laid the
foundations for the future definition of the "crime against
humanity" as a "crime under the law of nations" and to
universal jurisdiction over such crimes. |
Faculty of Economics and Social Science Home Page